11. Evaluative Language

Yet another rhetorical technique that is commonly encountered in  argumentation is the use of evaluative language to influence one’s audience to  accept the conclusion one is arguing for. Evaluative language can be contrasted  with descriptive language. Whereas descriptive language simply describes a  state of affairs, without passing judgment (positive or negative) on that state of  affairs, evaluative language is used to pass some sort of judgment, positive or  negative, on something. Contrast the following two statements:

Bob is tall.

Bob is good.

“Tall” is a descriptive term since being tall is, in itself, neither a good nor bad thing. Rather, it is a purely descriptive term that does not pass any sort of  judgment, positive or negative, on the fact that Bob is tall. In contrast, “good”  is a purely evaluative term, which means that the only thing the word does is  make an evaluation (in this case, a positive evaluation) and doesn’t carry any  descriptive content. “Good,” “bad,” “right,” and “wrong” are examples of  purely evaluative terms. The interesting kinds of terms are those that are both descriptive and evaluative. For example:

Bob is nosy.

“Nosy” is a negatively evaluative term since to call someone nosy is to make a  negative evaluation of them—or at least of that aspect of them. But it also  implies a descriptive content, such as that Bob is curious about other people’s  affairs. We could re-describe Bob’s nosiness using purely descriptive language:


Bob is very curious about other people’s affairs.


Notice that while the phrase “very curious about other people’s affairs” does  capture the descriptive sense of “nosy,” it doesn’t capture the evaluative sense  of nosy, since it doesn’t carry with it the negative connotation that “nosy” does.

Evaluative language is rife in our society, perhaps especially so in political  discourse. This isn’t surprising since by using evaluative language to describe  certain persons, actions, or events we can influence how people understand and  interpret the world. If you can get a person to think of someone or some state  of affairs in terms of a positively or negatively evaluative term, chances are you  will be able to influence their evaluation of that person or state of affairs. That is  one of the rhetorical uses of evaluative language. Compare, for example, 


Bob is a rebel.

Bob is a freedom fighter.


Whereas “rebel” tends to be a negatively evaluative term, “freedom fighter,” at  least for many Americans, tends to be a positively evaluative term. Both words,  however, have the same descriptive content, namely, that Bob is someone who  has risen in armed resistance to an existing government. The difference is that  whereas “rebel” makes a negative evaluation, “freedom fighter” makes a  positive evaluation. Table 3 below gives a small sampling of some evaluative  terms.


Table 3

beautiful

dangerous wasteful

 

sneaky

cute

murder

prudent

courageous timid

 

nosy

sloppy

smart

capable

insane

curt

 

 

English contains an interesting mechanism for turning positively evaluative terms  into negative evaluative ones. All you have to do is put the word “too” before a  positively evaluative terms and it will all of a sudden take on a negative  connotation. Compare the following:


John is honest.

John is too honest.


Whereas “honest” is a positively evaluative term, “too honest” is a negatively  evaluative term. When someone describes John as “too honest,” we can easily  imagine that person going on to describe how John’s honesty is actually a  liability or negative trait. Not so when he is simply described as honest. Since  the word “too” indicates an excess, and to say that something is an excess is to  make a criticism, we can see why the word “too” changes the valence of an  evaluation from positive to negative.

Evaluative language provides a good illustration of the difference between logic,  which is concerned with the analysis and evaluation of arguments, and rhetoric,  which is concerned with persuasion more generally. There are many ways that  humans can be caused to believe things besides through rational  argumentation. In fact, sometimes these other persuasive techniques are much  more effective. (Consider advertising techniques in the 1950s, which more often  tried to used argument and evidence to convince consumers to buy products,  compared to advertising today, which rarely uses argument and evidence.) In  any case, evaluative language—especially the use of hybrid terms that have  both descriptive and evaluative aspects—can lead people to subtly accept a  claim without ever arguing for it. As an analogy for how this could work in  conversation, consider the concept of what philosophers4 have called  “presupposition.” If is say something like

Even Jane could pass

I have asserted that Jane could pass the course. But I have also presupposed  that Jane is not a very good student (or not very smart) by using the word  “even.” If I were to say “nuh-uh,” this would naturally be taken as rejecting the  claim that Jane could pass (i.e., I would be saying that she couldn’t pass). And if  I were to agree, I would naturally be taken as agreeing that she could pass. But  notice that there isn’t any simply yes/no way to disagree with the presupposition  that Jane isn’t a smart/good student. Since presuppositions are more difficult  to challenge, they can end up influencing what people in the conversation are  taking for granted and in this way presupposition can influence what people  accept as true without any argument or evidence. Of course, a person could  explicitly challenge the implicit presupposition that Jane isn’t smart or a good  student, but that takes extra effort and many times people don’t realize that a presupposition has just slipped into a conversation.

I suggest that hybrid evaluative/descriptive terms can work as a kind of  presupposition. If I describe someone as an “insurgent,” for example, I am  saying something both descriptive—person who has risen in armed resistance  against an existing government—and negatively evaluative since the  connotation of the term “insurgent” (as compared to “freedom fighter”) has  come to be that of someone doing something bad or negative. In using the  term “insurgent” no one has explicitly claimed that the individual/group in  question is bad, but because the term has (for us) a negative connotation it can  lead us to be more receptive to accepting (implicitly) claims such as that the  person/group is bad or is doing something bad/harmful. 

Thus, like assuring and discounting (section 1.10), evaluative language is a  rhetorical technique. As such, it is more concerned with non-rational persuasion than it is with giving reasons. Non-rational persuasion is ubiquitous in our  society today, not the least of which because advertising is ubiquitous and  advertising today almost always uses non-rational persuasion. Think of the last  time you saw some commercial present evidence for why you should buy their  product (i.e., never) and you will realize how pervasive this kind of rhetoric is.  Philosophy has a complicated relationship with rhetoric—a relationship that stretches back to Ancient Greece. Socrates disliked those, such as the Sophists,  who promised to teach people how to effectively persuade someone of  something, regardless of whether that thing was true. Although some people  might claim that there is no essential difference between giving reasons for  accepting a conclusion and trying to persuade by any means, most  philosophers, including the author of this text, think otherwise. If we define  rhetoric as the art of persuasion, then although argumentation is a kind of  rhetoric (since it is a way of persuading), not all rhetoric is argumentation. The  essential difference, as already hinted at, is that argumentation attempts to  persuade by giving reasons whereas rhetoric attempts to persuade by any  means, including non-rational means. If I tell you over and over again (in  creative and subliminal ways) to drink Beer x because Beer x is the best beer,  then I may very well make you think that Beer x is the best beer, but I have not  thereby given you a reason to accept that Beer x is the best beer. Thinking of it  rationally, the mere fact that I’ve told you lots of times that Beer x is the best  beer gives you no good reason for believing that Beer x is in fact the best beer. 

The rhetorical devices surveyed in the last two sections may be effective ways of  persuading people, but they are not the same thing as offering an argument.

And if we attempt to see them as arguments, they turn out to be pretty poor  arguments. One of the many things that psychologists study is how we are  persuaded to believe or do things. As an empirical science, psychology  attempts to describe and explain the way things are, in this case, the processes  that lead us to believe or act as we do. Logic, in contrast, is not an empirical  science. Logic is not trying to tell us how we do think, but what good thinking is  and, thus, how we ought think. The study of logic is the study of the nature of  arguments and, importantly, of what distinguishes a good argument from a bad one. “Good” and “bad” are what philosophers call normative concepts because they involve standards of evaluation.5 Since logic concerns what makes  something a good argument, logic is sometimes referred to as a normative  science. They key standard of evaluation of arguments that we have seen so far  is that of validity. In chapter 2 we will consider some more precise, formal  methods of understanding validity. Other “normative sciences” include ethics  (the study of what a good life is and how we ought to live) and epistemology  (the study of what we have good reason to believe).


                                                        

For example, see David Lewis’s “Scorekeeping in a Language Game” (1979).